Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 13, No. 3, May 2018, pp. 268-274

Analytic atheism: A cross-culturally weak and fickle phenomenon?

Will M. Gervais*   Michiel van Elk#   Dimitris Xygalatas$   Ryan T. McKayX   Mark AveyardY   Emma E. Buchtel||   Ilan Dar-Nimrod**   Eva Kundtová Klocová##   Jonathan E. Ramsay$$   Tapani Riekkia   Annika M. Svedholm-Häkkinena   Joseph Bulbuliab

Religious belief is a topic of longstanding interest to psychological science, but the psychology of religious disbelief is a relative newcomer. One prominently discussed model is analytic atheism, wherein cognitive reflection, as measured with the Cognitive Reflection Test, overrides religious intuitions and instruction. Consistent with this model, performance-based measures of cognitive reflection predict religious disbelief in WEIRD (Western, Educated, Industrialized, Rich, & Democratic) samples. However, the generality of analytic atheism remains unknown. Drawing on a large global sample (N = 3461) from 13 religiously, demographically, and culturally diverse societies, we find that analytic atheism as usually assessed is in fact quite fickle cross-culturally, appearing robustly only in aggregate analyses and in three individual countries. The results provide additional evidence for culture’s effects on core beliefs.


Keywords: atheism; cultural learning; dual process cognition; religious cognition; replicability; WEIRD people; culture

1  Introduction

Are analytic thinkers less religious than people who follow their gut intuitions? Prominent atheists argue that rejection of religion primarily arises from their superior analytic prowess (e.g., Dawkins, 2006). In support of this analytic atheism conjecture, small but stable correlations between intelligence — itself associated with analytic thinking and cognitive reflection — and religious disbelief have been observed (Zuckerman, Silberman & Hall, 2013). Additionally, atheism is overrepresented amongst elite scientists as compared with non-elite scientists and non-scientists (Larson & Witham, 1998).

Drawing on dual process theories of human cognition (Evans, 2003) and work on the putatively intuitive roots of religious belief (e.g., Atran & Norenzayan, 2004; Bloom, 2007; Boyer, 2008), three independent teams published highly similar findings in 2012, observing that individuals who perform better on a commonly used behavioral measure of cognitive reflection, the Cognitive Reflection Test (CRT, Frederick, 2005), tend to report lower levels of religious belief and have a higher probability of self-identifying as atheists (Gervais & Norenzayan, 2012; Pennycook, Cheyne, Seli, Koehler & Fugelsang, 2012; Shenhav, Rand & Greene, 2012). Additionally, two of the teams reported that subtle experimental prods designed to nudge people to think more analytically also led them to report lower levels of religious belief (Gervais & Norenzayan, 2012; Shenhav et al., 2012). These results were taken as strong support for analytic atheism, and received widespread attention, both within academia (averaging over 240 citations apiece as of December 2017, via Google Scholar) and within popular culture (one article is among the top articles ever scored by Altmetrics). This pioneering research on analytic atheism spawned numerous follow-ups, and a recent meta-analysis of all 31 known studies (total N > 15000) on the topic found a stable, albeit small, negative correlation between cognitive reflection and religious belief (Pennycook, Ross, Koehler & Fugelsang, 2016).

Despite widespread enthusiasm for analytic atheism, there are several reasons to be skeptical about the mechanisms suggested by its proponents. First, there is only one known successful replication of any of the early experimental work suggesting that subtle primes for cognitive reflection actually increase atheism (Yilmaz, Karadöller & Sofuoglu, 2016). Second, independent investigations have found that other experimental prods to think analytically do not reliably reduce religiosity (Yonker, Edman, Cresswell & Barrett, 2016). Third, one multi-site, preregistered study (Sanchez, Sundermeier, Gray & Calin-Jageman, 2017) did not replicate one of the early experimental studies (Gervais & Norenzayan, 2012, Study 2). Recent work also questions the supposedly intuitive underpinnings of religious cognition (Farias et al., 2017). More fundamental, however, the clear majority of work on cognitive style and religious belief has taken place in North America, either in university settings or via Mechanical Turk, with rare exceptions (Yilmaz et al., 2016; Yilmaz & Saribay, 2016). Even if a correlation between cognitive reflection and religious disbelief turns out to be supported in North America, the degree to which such processes generalize widely beyond WEIRD (Western, Educated, Industrialized, Rich, Democratic: Henrich, Heine & Norenzayan, 2010) cultural contexts is still largely unknown. Certain features of religious beliefs vary strongly by culture (Purzycki et al., 2016), while others appear to be relatively stable (Gervais et al., 2017). It would be fortuitous and elegant if a parsimonious explanation of religious disbelief arising from cognitive reflection were generalizable to all or most cultures. However, set against a wider empirical background, the degree to which we can generalize the North American analytic atheism findings — both the unsettled experimental work, and the reliable but small correlations — remains an open question.

A strong version of the analytic atheism thesis is that analytic cognitive style and cognitive reflection should generally predict lower belief in gods. This predictive effect should be both substantial and universal. That is, the strong version of analytic atheism specifies that analytic thinking and cognitive reflection are primary drivers of atheism worldwide, implying that the magnitude of effect sizes must be more than modest. Further, a strong version of analytic atheism does not easily predict cross-cultural heterogeneity in the magnitude of the predictive effect of cognitive reflection on religious disbelief.

Here, we systematically evaluate the association between cognitive reflection and religious disbelief across 13 religiously, demographically, and culturally diverse societies. Sampled societies range from highly religious countries such as India to highly secular countries such as the Netherlands and China. Societies also differ in their majority religious composition, from Buddhist (Singapore), to Christian (USA), to Hindu (Mauritius), to Muslim (United Arab Emirates), to nonreligious (Czech Republic) traditions, and others. This multi-site design allows us to step beyond debates about mere replicability by additionally assessing the cross-cultural generalizability of a widely-discussed mechanism underlying atheism.


Table 1: Brief demographics of samples in 13 countries. CRT scores reflects the number of correct answers provided on the CRT out of 3 possible; higher scores reflect greater cognitive reflection. Belief in God was rated from 0–100.
CountryNMean Age [SD]Mean CRT [SD]Mean Belief [SD]Source
Australia14320.11 [5.34]1.28 [1.20]54.82 [38.83]students
China20729.82 [5.95]1.80 [1.04]28.74 [35.71]community
Czech Republic18721.96 [2.09]1.06 [0.87]47.23 [39.88]students
Finland99228.15 [8.23]1.76 [1.10]31.28 [35.32]mixed
Hong Kong12821.01 [2.97]1.37 [1.13]62.94 [36.20]students
India22430.79 [8.38]1.42 [1.17]85.69 [25.70]community
Mauritius16121.73 [1.33]1.13 [0.97]76.46 [39.21]community
Netherlands21219.49 [2.14]1.12 [1.03]21.23 [29.96]students
New Zealand16023.06 [7.98]1.24 [1.11]41.48 [39.84]students
Singapore16120.83 [1.69]1.83 [1.01]69.75 [30.39]students
UAE14519.92 [1.57]0.63 [0.93]94.24 [19.04]students
UK15025.33 [9.60]1.30 [1.20]34.26 [36.90]students
USA59119.36 [3.07]0.77 [1.04]79.55 [32.04]students

2  Method

Participants in all 13 countries completed the CRT, and a face-valid item of religious belief, rating strength in belief in God or gods from 0 (definitely does not exist) to 100 (definitely exists). Crucially, both the CRT and the belief in God(s) item were used in one of the initial studies on cognitive reflection and religion (Gervais & Norenzayan, 2012, Study 1) allowing for direct replication, comparison, and extension. The countries were convenience sampled1, but selected to represent a broad range of religious backgrounds. Most participants were young, and 9 samples were students (Table 1). Data from 12 countries were obtained from an existing dataset from a previous unrelated project (Gervais et al., 2017), while United States data were taken from a larger university sample, allowing increased estimate precision. Participants in China and India were directly paid for their participation; Australia, Czech Republic, Hong Kong, the Netherlands, New Zealand, Singapore, United Arab Emirates, the United Kingdom, and the USA were student samples participating either for course credit or to be enrolled in a lottery. The Indian participants were recruited from Mechanical Turk and were screened to include only participants who reported not having previously done the CRT. Additional demographic and methodological details are available in a supplement at https://osf.io/p5h6s/.

We note that the present study was not fully preregistered, although our initial recruitment and preregistration in the original project (https://osf.io/f6tcr/) did mention the possibility of using collected data to run the present analyses separately. In total, we analyzed data from 3461 participants (69% female) across 13 countries.2 This number far exceeds the sample size of most social psychological research (including research on this topic) and provides an adequate sample size for good estimate precision on the aggregate analysis. In addition, our per-country sample sizes were on par with previous analytic atheism research. Table 1 displays descriptive statistics for each country’s data. Data and code are available at https://osf.io/v53c4/.

3  Results


Table 2: Full summary of model coefficients. Mean = posterior mean, SD = posterior standard deviation, lower and upper refer to the lower and upper bounds of a 95% highest posterior density interval. ρ refers to the covariance between model intercepts and βs (betas) across countries. Standardized βs for slopes appear in brackets.
 
Mean
SD
lower
upper
Intercepts
Total
55.95
6.66
42.66
69.08
Australia
54.70
2.84
49.07
60.19
China
30.71
2.55
25.70
35.69
Czech
47.58
2.51
42.65
52.49
Finland
31.65
1.21
29.28
34.02
Hong Kong
62.23
2.98
56.40
68.09
India
85.92
2.35
81.31
90.49
Mauritius
77.05
2.70
71.72
82.31
Netherlands
21.19
2.38
16.49
25.81
New Zealand
41.69
2.66
36.45
46.89
Singapore
72.43
2.90
66.71
78.11
UAE
91.75
3.17
85.65
98.06
UK
34.65
2.75
29.19
39.98
USA
77.17
1.60
74.03
80.31
Unstandardized βs
Female
3.07
0.60
1.91
4.24
Age
−0.10  
0.70
−1.45  
1.29
 Mean       SDlower   upper    
CRT      
Total−1.89 [−.05]  1.06−4.00 [−.12]0.22 [   .02]
Austr.−4.59 [−.14]  2.00−8.60 [−.26]−0.94 [−.03]
China−2.44 [−.07]  1.82−6.11 [−.17]1.05 [   .03]
Czech0.58 [   .03]  2.12−3.33 [−.09]4.88 [   .15]
Finland−1.18 [−.03]  0.92−2.99 [−.08]0.63 [   .02]
H.K.−1.83 [−.05]  1.86−5.44 [−.16]1.98 [   .06]
India−2.81 [−.08]  1.59−5.88 [−.17]0.37 [   .01]
Maurit.−2.85 [−.08]  1.92−6.70 [−.19]0.97 [   .03]
Neth.0.24 [   .01]  1.79−3.24 [−.09]3.81 [   .11]
N.Z.0.05 [   .01]  1.85−3.40 [−.09]3.84 [   .11]
Sing.−5.55 [−.17]  2.24−10.00 [−.30]−1.41 [−.05]
UAE−3.46 [−.10]  2.09−7.65 [−.23]0.66 [   .02]
UK2.55 [   .09]  2.21−1.64 [−.03]6.86 [   .21]
USA−3.40 [−.10]  1.20−5.78 [−.16]−1.08 [−.03]
ρ(Int.,β)−0.390.26−0.85.12

We conducted a Bayesian hierarchical (multilevel) model (fit by the R package from McElreath, 2016, version 1.59) that provides parameter estimates within each country, as well as an overall estimate that is directly equivalent to performing a meta-analysis on the whole dataset (Vuorre, 2017). Bayesian analyses offer many benefits (Wagenmakers, Morey & Lee, 2016) such as producing intuitive probability statements for the credibility of different parameter estimates, contingent on data and model (Kruschke, 2010; McElreath, 2016). We used non-informative and mildly regularizing priors, primarily deployed to combat model overfitting (McElreath, 2016). In addition, the Bayesian hierarchical framework alleviates some concerns of multiple testing, which would be problematic when performing separate analyses on each of the 13 countries (Gelman, Hill & Yajima, 2012). Our final model treated intercepts and slopes of CRT as random across countries, and included age and gender as fixed covariates. These were the only variables shared and uniformly coded across all 13 sites.

The primary inference in Bayesian estimation is the full posterior distribution of all estimates. The posterior distribution indexes how plausible or credible it is that different potential parameters could have yielded the observed data. Figure 1 displays the posterior distributions for unstandardized betas, which represent the predicted change observed in individual belief in God as performance on the CRT increases by each additional correct answer. When interpreting posterior distributions, tighter and taller distributions reflect less estimate uncertainty than do flatter distributions, and the relative height along the curve indexes relative estimate credibility. For example, if the top of the curve is twice as tall as another point, that means that the estimate at the top of the curve is twice as good of a guess for the underlying parameter. Figure 1 also displays the posterior probability that cognitive reflection predicts nonzero and negative changes in belief in God. The posterior probability is in many ways analogous to how many intuitively misinterpret directional frequentist p-values: as the probability of a given effect existing (Oakes, 1986). In addition to the posterior distributions, Table 2 also summarizes the posterior predictions with the posterior mean as a point estimate and uncertainty around this estimate reflected by highest posterior density intervals (HPDI), which index the range in which the 95% most credible estimates lie. This is similar to how frequentist confidence intervals are often intuitively misinterpreted (Hoekstra, Morey, Rouder & Wagenmakers, 2014).


Figure 1: Cognitive reflection predicting belief in God across 13 countries. Plot shows the posterior distribution for unstandardized betas, as well as the posterior probability that CRT performance predicts lower religious belief across sites. Estimate precision is largely driven by per-country sample size (Table 2).

As Table 2 illustrates, and consistent with the cross-cultural psychology of religion, there was substantial heterogeneity in average belief in God across sites (random intercepts). The posterior probabilities in the right of Figure 1 show relatively strong overall evidence for a CRT-disbelief link aggregating across all countries, but among individual countries only Australia, Singapore, and the USA show unequivocal evidence of a CRT-religious disbelief link. New Zealand, the Netherlands, and the Czech Republic produced almost perfectly equivocal evidence of analytic atheism (posterior probabilities of basically .5) and the UK actually shows moderate evidence of a sign reversal whereby analytic thinkers were mildly more religious.3 Most of the posterior densities’ masses are quite close to zero, suggesting that any relationships between CRT performance and religious disbelief within countries were modest, in even the few cases where they were reliably evident.

Given the non-standardized and non-representative sampling strategies employed across sites, and the predominance of students in the samples, we are reluctant to over-interpret potential causes for why the CRT-disbelief relationship is so fickle across sites. However, our model estimates a .92 posterior probability of an inverse relationship between slopes and intercepts indicating that the analytic atheism relationship was apparently strongest in sites more reliably religious (Figure 2, Table 2).4 Speculating, it is possible that cognitive reflection measures are tapping a tendency to question prevailing cultural norms. In cultures where institutional religion is waning and where acceptance of atheism arises from tendencies to conform, it is possible that cognitive reflection may predict the rejection of atheism, a matter for future investigation. Here, we infer only that the relationship between cognitive reflection and disbelief is globally both weak and fickle.


Figure 2: Posterior summaries for the average belief within each country and the unstandardized beta within each country. Model predicts a stronger relationship between CRT and religious disbelief in more religious countries. X-axis depicts modeled random intercepts, y-axis depicts modeled random slopes. Vertical lines reflect 95% HPDIs in betas and horizontal lines reflect 95% HPDIs in intercepts.

4  Discussion

Models for an inverse relationship between cognitive reflection and religious belief — here termed analytic atheism — have sparked both scholarly and popular interest. However, the magnitude and cross-cultural generalizability of this relationship has not to date been thoroughly and directly investigated. Here, we report data from 13 diverse countries, and find quite mixed evidence. At the aggregate level, our model predicts a .96 probability that cognitive reflection is associated with religious disbelief. Though reliable, this effect is small, as after adjusting for country-level dependencies each additional correct CRT item predicts a reduction in belief in God of less than 2 points on a scale of 0 to 100, standardized β = −.05 [−.12, .02]. Within individual countries, cognitive reflection was, at best, a fickle predictor of religious disbelief. Four relatively secular countries — New Zealand, the Netherlands, the Czech Republic, and the UK — did not even produce estimates that were reliably directionally consistent with the analytic atheist thesis. When a relationship between cognitive reflection and religious disbelief was strongly apparent (in aggregate across sites, and within Australia, Singapore, and the USA) or hinted at (in the bulk of sampled countries), this relationship was quite modest in magnitude, yielding standardized betas that hovered at −0.10 or weaker. Thus, cognitive reflection may not actually be an especially potent global predictor of atheism.

4.1  Future Questions and Constraints on Generality

The present paper utilized the CRT as a sole measure of cognitive reflection. The CRT is widely used, but may not measure the most relevant sort of reflection very well (Baron, Scott, Fincher, & Metz, 2015). Similar and convergent measures of analytic thinking and cognitive reflection also similarly predict religious disbelief (Pennycook, Cheyne, Barr, Koehler & Fugelsang, 2014a; Saribay & Yilmaz, 2017), bolstering the claims to generalizability across measures and also, possibly, providing more direct measures of the relevant traits. Likewise, the single-item belief measure is potentially problematic. There are may ways to “believe in God”, some of which may be impervious to any sort of reflection. Cognitive reflection differentially predicts different facets of religiosity (Bahçekapili & Yilmaz, 2017), as well as religious affiliation (Pennycook et al., 2012) and other related constructs (Pennycook, Cheyne, Barr, Koehler & Fugelsang, 2014b; Saribay & Yilmaz, 2017; Yilmaz & Saribay, 2016). And other measures of reflection, as well as CRT items, predict specific religious beliefs such as endorsement of “divine command theory” Piazza & Landy, 2013; Baron et al., 2015), a view that explicitly discourages reflection on the ground that the word of God is beyond human understanding.

The present paper can serve as a jumping board for additional cross-cultural exploration. The present results move well past the WEIRD samples (Henrich et al., 2010) that exemplify social psychology. Although we used a relatively large cross-cultural sample, our findings would benefit from extension to other contexts, such as small-scale, hunter-gatherer communities, or older adults. In addition, our results present only suggestive evidence for the factors predicting cross-cultural differences in analytic atheism. Given that the strongest effects in the present study tended to emerge from highly religious societies and that our sampling is, if anything, skewed towards highly secular societies, we may well observe more robust evidence of analytic atheism in other samples from highly religious societies. We would expect that strength of cultural support for religion and analytic atheism interacts: without some sufficient level of cultural support, there may be no need for people to analytically override religious impulses and instruction. Furthermore, if cognitive reflection (or some other measure) were tapping a capacity to question prevailing cultural norms, it is possible that cognitive reflection may predict the rejection of institutional atheism in some highly secular contexts.

4.2  Coda

Though Homo sapiens is a religious species, atheism exists in all known societies, and is growing increasingly prevalent across industrial societies — perhaps to an underappreciated level due to underreporting (Gervais & Najle, 2018). Researchers have theorized that analytic thinking and cognitive reflection are engines of religious skepticism. Consistent evidence for a positive association between cognitive reflection and religious disbelief has been primarily found in WEIRD samples. The present study provides a broader cross-cultural evaluation of analytic atheism. We observe that the analytic thinking model of religious disbelief (e.g., Bloom, 2007; Boyer, 2008) may overstate the magnitude and cross-cultural generalizability of any relationship between cognitive reflection and atheism as usually measured. In our view, these results outright falsify two claims central to a strong version of analytic atheism: the effect is neither consistent across cultures nor large enough to be a primary driver of atheism in the simple way we and many others have measured it. Indeed, according to the present results, if one wants to predict a stranger’s degree of religious belief, they may be better off knowing where the stranger is from rather than how analytically the stranger thinks. Speculatively, it is possible that cognitive reflection is related to a tendency to challenge culturally dominant orthodoxies in general. However, whether this is so, and where the causal arrows flow, are matters for future cultural psychological research. For now, the present study contributes to psychological science in challenging the ubiquity of the analytic atheism model, while also contributing to growing awareness about the limitations of inferring human universals from WEIRD samples, and demonstrating the power of cross-cultural approaches to clarify how core beliefs arise from an interplay of individual differences and local cultures.

References

Atran, S., & Norenzayan, A. (2004). Religion’s evolutionary landscape: Counterintuition, commitment, compassion, communion. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27(06), 713–730.

Bahçekapili, H. G., & Yilmaz, O. (2017). The relation between different types of religiosity and analytic cognitive style. Personality and Individual Differences, 117, 267–272.

Baron, J., Scott, S., Fincher, K., & Metz, S. E. (2015). Why does the Cognitive Reflection Test (sometimes) predict utilitarian moral judgment (and other things)? Journal of Applied Research in Memory and Cognition, 4(3), 265–284.

Bloom, P. (2007). Religion is natural. Developmental Science, 10(1), 147–151.

Boyer, P. (2008). Being human: Religion: Bound to believe? Nature, 455(7216), 1038–1039.

Dawkins, R. (2006). The god delusion. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Co.

Evans, J. S. T. (2003). In two minds: Dual-process accounts of reasoning. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(10), 454–459. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2003.08.012.

Farias, M., van Mulukom, V., Kahane, G., Kreplin, U., Joyce, A., Soares, P., …Savulescu, J. (2017). Supernatural belief is not modulated by intuitive thinking style or cognitive inhibition. Scientific Reports, 7, Article 15100. http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/s41598-017-14090-9.

Frederick, S. (2005). Cognitive reflection and decision making. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 19(4), 25–42. http://dx.doi.org/10.1257/089533005775196732.

Gelman, A., Hill, J., & Yajima, M. (2012). Why we (usually) don’t have to worry about multiple comparisons. Journal of Research on Educational Effectiveness, 5(2), 189–211.

Gervais, W. M., & Najle, M. B. (2018). How many atheists are there. Socia Psychological and Personality Science, 9, 3–11.

Gervais, W. M., & Norenzayan, A. (2012). Analytic thinking promotes religious disbelief. Science, 336(6080), 493–496.

Gervais, W. M., Xygalatas, D., McKay, R. T., van Elk, M., Buchtel, E. E., Aveyard, M., …Riekki, T. (2017). Global evidence of extreme intuitive moral prejudice against atheists. Nature Human Behaviour, 1(8), s41562–41017–40151.

Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. (2010). The weirdest people in the world? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33(2–3), 61–83.

Hoekstra, R., Morey, R. D., Rouder, J. N., & Wagenmakers, E.-J. (2014). Robust misinterpretation of confidence intervals. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 21(5), 1157–1164.

Kruschke, J. K. (2010). Doing bayesian data analysis: A tutorial introduction with r. New York: Academic Press.

Larson, E. J., & Witham, L. (1998). Leading scientists still reject god. Nature, 394(6691), 313–313.

McElreath, R. (2016). Statistical rethinking: A bayesian course with examples in r and stan. Chapman & Hall/CRC texts in statistical science series; 122. (R package: https://github.com/rmcelreath/rethinking).

Oakes, M. (1986). Statistical inference: A commentary for the social and behavioral sciences. New York: Wiley.

Pennycook, G., Cheyne, J. A., Barr, N., Koehler, D. J., & Fugelsang, J. A. (2014a). Cognitive style and religiosity: The role of conflict detection. Memory & Cognition, 42(1), 1–10.

Pennycook, G., Cheyne, J. A., Barr, N., Koehler, D. J., & Fugelsang, J. A. (2014b). The role of analytic thinking in moral judgements and values. Thinking & Reasoning, 20(2), 188–214.

Pennycook, G., Cheyne, J. A., Seli, P., Koehler, D. J., & Fugelsang, J. A. (2012). Analytic cognitive style predicts religious and paranormal belief. Cognition, 123(3), 335–346.

Pennycook, G., Ross, R. M., Koehler, D. J., & Fugelsang, J. A. (2016). Atheists and agnostics are more reflective than religious believers: Four empirical studies and a meta-analysis. PLoS One, 11(4), e0153039.

Piazza, J., & Landy, J. F. (2013). "Lean not on your own understanding": Belief that morality is founded on divine authority and non-utilitarian moral judgments. Judgment and Decision Making, 8, 639–661

Purzycki, B. G., Apicella, C., Atkinson, Q. D., Cohen, E., McNamara, R. A., Willard, A. K., …& Henrich, J. (2016). Moralistic gods, supernatural punishment and the expansion of human sociality. Nature, 530(7590), 327–330.

Sanchez, C., Sundermeier, B., Gray, K., & Calin-Jageman, R. J. (2017). Direct replication of gervais & norenzayan (2012): No evidence that analytic thinking decreases religious belief. PLoS One, 12(2), e0172636.

Saribay, S. A., & Yilmaz, O. (2017). Analytic cognitive style and cognitive ability differentially predict religiosity and social conservatism. Personality and Individual Differences, 114, 24–29.

Shenhav, A., Rand, D. G., & Greene, J. D. (2012). Divine intuition: Cognitive style influences belief in god. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 141(3), 423.

Vuorre, M. (2017). Meta-analysis is a special case of bayesian multilevel modeling | matti vuorre. Retrieved from https://mvuorre.github.io/post/2016/2016-09-29-bayesian-meta-analysis/.

Wagenmakers, E.-J., Morey, R. D., & Lee, M. D. (2016). Bayesian benefits for the pragmatic researcher. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 25(3), 169–176.

Yilmaz, O., Karadöller, D. Z., & Sofuoglu, G. (2016). Analytic thinking, religion, and prejudice: An experimental test of the dual-process model of mind. The International Journal for the Psychology of Religion, 26(4), 360–369.

Yilmaz, O., & Saribay, S. A. (2016). An attempt to clarify the link between cognitive style and political ideology: A non-western replication and extension. Judgment and Decision Making, 11(3), 287–300.

Yonker, J. E., Edman, L. R., Cresswell, J., & Barrett, J. L. (2016). Primed analytic thought and religiosity: The importance of individual characteristics. Psychology of Religion and Spirituality, 8(4), 298–308.

Zuckerman, M., Silberman, J., & Hall, J. A. (2013). The relation between intelligence and religiosity: A meta-analysis and some proposed explanations. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 17(4), 325–354.


*
University of Kentucky (USA). Email: will.gervais@uky.edu.
#
University of Amsterdam (Netherlands).
$
University of Connecticut (USA).
X
Royal Holloway, University of London (UK)
Y
American University of Sharjah (United Arab Emirates).
||
Education University of Hong Kong (Hong Kong).
**
The University of Sydney (Australia).
##
Masaryk University (Czech Republic).
$$
Singapore University of Social Sciences (Singapore).
a
University of Helsinki (Finland)
b
Victoria University of Wellington (New Zealand).

This research was supported by a grant to WMG from the Templeton Foundation (48275). JB was supported by grants from the Templeton World Charity Foundation (0077), and a Royal Society of New Zealand Marsden Grant (VUW1321). DX acknowledges support by the Interacting Minds Centre at Aarhus University. RMcK acknowledges the support of the John Templeton Foundation (52257), and the ARC Centre of Excellence in Cognition and its Disorders at Macquarie University. MvE acknowledges support by a VENI grant (016.135.135) from the Dutch Organization for Scientific Research. The content is solely the responsibility of the authors and does not necessarily represent the official views of its funders. The funders had no role in study design, data collection and analysis, decision to publish, or preparation of the manuscript.

WMG developed the study design in consultation with all the authors. WMG performed the analyses and prepared the figures. WMG, MvE, JB, DX, and RMcK wrote the manuscript with input from all authors. All authors collected data.
Copyright: © 2018. The authors license this article under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License.

1
They are basically countries where Gervais had contacts.
2
4051 participants completed at least some of the questions. 384 participants were omitted because they failed an attention check. After omitting these participants, participants who provided responses outside of acceptable ranges, and participants who did not complete all measures of interest were omitted; 3461 participants were retained for full analyses.
3
To test heterogeneity of the CRT effect across countries, we compared two models fit with the lmer() function in the lme4 R package. One model regressed belief in god on CRT score, with a random effect for country and a random slope for CRT within country. The other was the same but without the random slope. The different was significant at p<.006 by analysis of variance.
4
In a post-hoc regression across the 13 countries, with a measure of analytic atheism (the CRT effect) as the dependent variable and two predictors, mean CRT score and mean belief in God, the effect of belief in God was highly significant (p < .005), supporting the observation that the effect is largest in the less secular countries. Mean CRT score had no effect.

This document was translated from LATEX by HEVEA.